Are We Really So Modern?
For all our technological breakthroughs, we’re still wrestling with the same basic questions as the Enlightenment philosophers.
We
like to think of ourselves as living in an age of unprecedented
disruption. Just look at all the commonplace features of our world that
didn’t exist a century ago—jet travel, television, space flight, the
Internet. If you could transport someone from the year 1916 to the
present, we ask a little proudly, wouldn’t that person be stupefied by
the changes? And, of course, he would be, at least for a few days, until
he figured out how everything worked. But one thing would be very
familiar to such a time traveller: the pride, and the anxiety, we feel
about being so modern. For people in the early twentieth century were as
acutely aware of their modernity as we are of ours, and with just as
good reason. After all, they might have said, imagine someone
transported from 1816 to 1916: what would that person have thought of
railroads, telegraphs, machine guns, and steamships?
Modernity
cannot be identified with any particular technological or social
breakthrough. Rather, it is a subjective condition, a feeling or an
intuition that we are in some profound sense different from the people
who lived before us. Modern life, which we tend to think of as an
accelerating series of gains in knowledge, wealth, and power over
nature, is predicated on a loss: the loss of contact with the past.
Depending on your point of view, this can be seen as either a
disinheritance or an emancipation; much of modern politics is determined
by which side you take on this question. But it is always disorienting.
If
we are looking for the real origins of the modern world, then, we have
to look for the moment when that world was literally
disoriented—stripped of its sense of direction. Heliocentrism, the
doctrine that the earth revolves around the sun rather than vice versa,
was announced by Copernicus in 1543 and championed by Galileo in the
early sixteen-hundreds. This revelation was immediately experienced as a
profound dislocation, as John Donne testified in his 1611 poem “An
Anatomy of the World”: “The sun is lost, and th’ earth, and no man’s
wit / Can well direct him where to look for it.” More than two hundred
and fifty years later, Nietzsche was reeling from the same cosmic loss
of direction: “What were we doing when we unchained this earth from its
sun? . . . Are we not plunging continually? Backward, sideward, forward,
in all directions? Is there still any up or down?” Modernity is a
vertigo that began in the sixteenth century and shows no sign of letting
up.
Nietzsche is usually
classified as a philosopher, Donne as a poet, and Galileo as a
scientist. But one of the premises of Anthony Gottlieb’s new book, “The
Dream of Enlightenment” (Liveright)—the second installment of his lucid,
accessible history of Western philosophy—is that thought cannot be
divided according to disciplines in this way. For philosophy, in
particular, such a division is misleading. Today, we tend to think of
philosophy as a specialized academic pursuit: a philosopher is a
professor of philosophy. But none of the founders of modern philosophy
whom Gottlieb discusses fit that description. Some were mathematicians:
René Descartes invented the Cartesian coördinate system with its x- and
y-axes, and Gottfried Leibniz invented calculus (around the same time
as, but independently of, Isaac Newton). Some were professionals: Baruch
Spinoza ground lenses for optical equipment; John Locke was a doctor
and a diplomat. And some were literary writers, like David Hume, who was
better known in his lifetime for his “History of England” than for his
philosophical works. Usually, they overlapped several categories.
One
of Gottlieb’s central insights is that, as he wrote in his previous
volume, “The Dream of Reason,” which covered thought from the Greeks to
the Renaissance, “the history of philosophy is more the history of a
sharply inquisitive cast of mind than the history of a sharply defined
discipline.” You might say that philosophy is what we call thought in
its first, molten state, before it has had a chance to solidify into a
scientific discipline, like psychology or cosmology. When scientists ask
how people think or how the universe was created, they are addressing
the same questions posed by philosophy hundreds or even thousands of
years earlier. This is why, Gottlieb observes, people complain that
philosophy never seems to be making progress: “Any corner of it that
comes generally to be regarded as useful soon ceases to be called
philosophy.”
Therefore, philosophy
shouldn’t be considered a kind of centuries-long chess match, with
thinkers taking turns in an abstract intellectual game. For instance, in
treating the philosophy of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, it
is conventional to cast it as a struggle between “rationalists” and
“empiricists.” In this account, everyone from Descartes to Hume is
engaged in one long battle over whether truth is to be found “in here,”
through strictly logical reasoning on the model of mathematics, or “out
there,” through observation of the world. This debate, in turn, was
finally resolved by Immanuel Kant, in the late eighteenth century, when
he figured out a way to show that both sides were correct, since all
perception is necessarily filtered through the categories imposed by our
minds.
There
is some truth to this account—the origin of knowledge was certainly a
concern for all these thinkers. But Gottlieb, who is not an academic and
spent much of his career as a journalist—he is a former executive
editor of The Economist—sees that they were situated in a much
wider world. Their thought was informed not just by previous philosophy
but by politics, religion, and science—the whole intellectual and
spiritual life of their times. And it was because these times were so
tumultuous that they were able to think in such a radical way. Eras in
which everything is up for grabs are very rare, and they seem to be
highly productive for philosophy. As Gottlieb points out, much of the
Western philosophy that still matters to us is the product of just two
such eras: Athens in the fifth and fourth centuries B.C. and Western
Europe in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries A.D.
It
is hard for us to comprehend how totally Western consciousness was
transformed during the second of these two periods, precisely because we
live in its aftermath. In just a few generations preceding it, every
fixed point that had oriented the world for thousands of years began to
wobble. The discovery of America destroyed established geography, the
Reformation destroyed the established Church, and astronomy destroyed
the established cosmos. Everything that educated people believed about
reality turned out to be an error or, worse, a lie. It’s impossible to
imagine what, if anything, could produce a comparable effect on us
today. Even the discovery of alien life in the universe wouldn’t do it,
since we have long learned to expect such a discovery, whereas medieval
Europeans could never have anticipated the existence of America, or of
electricity.
Perhaps if it were
somehow confirmed that, as some thinkers speculate, our universe is
actually a simulation run on a computer by an unfathomably advanced
intelligent civilization, we would feel an analogous sense of confusion
and possibility. That would raise the questions that were at the heart
of philosophy in both of Gottlieb’s magical periods in a new way. What
does it mean for something to be? Why does anything exist in the first
place? Such metaphysical questions are what, from the very beginning,
gave philosophy a bad name, because to practical-minded people they
appear useless. That is why the comic playwright Aristophanes, in his
play “The Clouds,” portrayed Socrates as discussing questions such as
whether a gnat buzzes through its nose or its anus. No one knows, sure,
but also no one cares.
Not caring
about things like being and meaning, however, is impossible, because
they are the fundamental concepts that structure our very experience of
the world. People who say they don’t care about metaphysics really mean
that their received ideas on such matters are so fixed that they have
disappeared from consciousness, in the same way that you don’t usually
notice your heartbeat. Philosophers are people who, for some
reason—Plato called it the sense of wonder—feel compelled to make the
obvious strange. When they try to communicate that basic, pervasive
strangeness or wonder to other people, they usually find that the other
people don’t like it. Sometimes, as with Socrates, they like it so
little that they put the philosopher to death. More often, however, they
just ignore him.
But the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries were one of those rare periods when
a lot of people cared, because their sense of the world was decomposing
so dramatically. Literate people—and, thanks to the printing press,
there were more of these than ever before—were eager to hear from
philosophers who could give new answers to the ancient questions. If
everything you thought you knew was wrong, how could you ever be
confident that your knowledge was correct? Where does knowledge come
from? What is matter made of? Is there a God, and, if so, what kind of
being is he?
These were the
questions that animated the philosophers discussed by Gottlieb, starting
with Descartes. Born in 1596, Descartes was what at the time would have
been called a “natural philosopher,” or what we would call a scientist.
His areas of expertise, in addition to mathematics, included optics,
physiology, and meteorology. He “was so fascinated by machines and all
kinds of mechanical contraptions,” Gottlieb writes, “that, according to a
piece of widespread gossip, he was often accompanied by a life-size
working doll that was practically indistinguishable from his
illegitimate daughter, Francine.”
This
rumor was a fitting one, since Descartes argued for a thoroughly
mechanistic view of nature. For centuries, Aristotelian science had
taught that the fundamental units of being were substances, in which
qualities or “accidents” were lodged: thus, a cow is a substance, the
redness of the cow an accident. Descartes abolished this distinction,
holding, instead, that everything physical that exists is simply matter
in space. The primary facts of nature are things like “heaviness and
hardness,” which are descriptions of the physical arrangement of matter.
Secondary qualities, such as “light and colors, sounds, smells,
tastes,” and so on, are subjective. They appear to human beings because
of the way our sensory apparatus is constructed, but they are not
inherent in the things themselves.
Another
way of putting this is that Descartes described reality in terms of
qualities that can be measured mathematically. Descartes himself was a
towering mathematician, but he was far from the first philosopher to
regard mathematics as the gold standard of truth: Pythagoras and Plato
had done so two thousand years before. In the dialogue known as the
Meno, Plato depicts Socrates teaching a slave boy the Pythagorean
theorem—or, rather, leading the boy to figure it out for himself. The
dialogue shows what is so seductive about mathematics, that each step
follows inevitably from the previous step, in a way that makes it
absolutely beyond doubt or error. You can get math wrong, but when
you’re right you know you’re right.
To
Plato, this could be explained by the fact that the soul had a life
before birth in which it learned mathematical truths, so that learning
is really a form of remembering. Descartes had no use for such a tale,
which raised far more questions than it answered. But he, too, was drawn
to the kind of certainty that mathematics offered, and in his
“Meditations” he claimed to have achieved it. Begin, Descartes wrote, by
doubting absolutely everything you know, think, and perceive; assume
that it is all delusive, as in a dream. Does anything remain absolutely
certain, even after this purge? One thing does, he argued: the fact of
my consciousness. If I did not exist as a mind, there would be no “I” to
be deceived by appearances. If I think, I must exist—Cogito ergo sum.
From
this fixed basis, Descartes believed that he could infallibly deduce
another crucial principle: the existence of a good God, who guarantees
the truth of my perceptions and so underwrites the existence of the
world. But here most people believe that Descartes went astray. “God’s
guarantee is not worth the paper Descartes wrote it on,” Gottlieb quips.
And, if God doesn’t exist, then all Descartes has done is leave the
individual trapped “in a prison of his own ideas,” unable to prove that
what he experiences has any basis in external reality. Indeed, Descartes
never found a satisfying solution to the problem of how mind and matter
interact. He famously identified the pineal gland as the point of
connection, though how a gland could have access to an immaterial mind
is far from clear.
Gottlieb
observes that Descartes would have been disappointed to know that he
gave rise to a whole new era of philosophy. He thought that there would
not have to be any philosophy after him, since he had solved all the
problems; only experimental research would remain. But while science
achieved amazing things in the years after Descartes—this was the age of
Newton’s discovery of gravity and Boyle’s invention of modern
chemistry—philosophy did not fall mute. The more that the new science
seemed to confirm Descartes’s mechanical picture of the universe, the
more necessary it became to ask what matter and mind really were and how
they fit together.
Some of the
answers that the best minds of the period came up with may now appear
bizarre. That is the case with Gottfried Leibniz, born in 1646, whom
Gottlieb calls “the greatest polymath since Aristotle.” When Leibniz
tried to tackle the problem of how mind and matter interact, he came up
with a radical new thesis: they don’t. Everything that exists, he
believed, is made up of units called monads, and these monads have
absolutely no way of impinging on or communicating with one
another—Leibniz referred to them as “windowless.” Each monad has its own
destiny, and it acts and moves entirely of its own accord. If the world
nonetheless appears to be a chain of causes and effects, that is
because the monads are programmed to behave in such a way that they seem
to be interacting. This “pre-established harmony” is guaranteed by a
beneficent God.
If philosophy is
defiance of common sense, then Leibniz’s ideas are very philosophical
indeed—too much so even for most of his fellow-philosophers. (Hegel
called them “a metaphysical romance.”) But he was driven to the apparent
absurdity of denying causality by his desperation to solve the problem
that Descartes couldn’t: How can immaterial mind affect material bodies,
and vice versa? Even today, cognitive scientists struggle to understand
how consciousness arises from matter, though few doubt that it does.
Likewise, the idea that, as Gottlieb writes, “physical bodies are . . .
not quite what they seem, but are only appearances somehow thrown up by
monads” seems less extravagant in the light of contemporary string
theory, which holds that everything that exists is the product of
vibrating one-dimensional objects. And both of these ideas can be seen
as refinements of the very first idea in Western philosophy, Thales’s
enigmatic statement that everything is water. In each case, theory
denies that the world as it appears is the fundamental reality, and
looks to something more original to explain it. To answer the questions
that philosophy asks, a long detour through science is necessary; but at
the beginning and the end of the journey we find the same sense of
wonder.
One of the most popular
names for the unexplainable is God: God is how we answer questions about
creation and purpose that we can’t answer in any other way. Certainly,
both Descartes and Leibniz relied on God to balance the equation of the
universe. Without him, they believed, the world did not make sense. The
philosophers’ God was not necessarily identical to the God of
Christianity, but he had some reassuringly familiar attributes, such as
beneficence and providential oversight of the world. But Baruch Spinoza,
another revolutionary thinker of the seventeenth century, went furthest
in reconceiving the idea of God, in ways so radical that his name
became a byword for dangerous atheism. Spinoza’s trouble with organized
religion started early: at the age of twenty-three, he was
excommunicated from the Jewish community of Amsterdam for his heretical
views.
His heresy, as developed
later in his magnum opus, “Ethics,” was not to deny the existence of
God. Instead, Spinoza made God so crucial to the world that the
distinction between the two collapsed. There could not be two substances
in the universe, Spinoza argued, one physical and the other divine,
since this involved a logical contradiction. If God and Nature were
distinct, then it must be the case that Nature had some qualities that
God lacked, and the idea of a supreme being lacking anything was
incoherent. It follows that God and Nature are just two names for the
same thing, the Being that comprises everything that ever existed or
ever will exist.
This
radical idea, known as pantheism, has strange and paradoxical results.
On the one hand, it divinizes the universe, meaning that it brings God
very close to us—indeed, it says that we ourselves are part of God. On
the other hand, an immanent God is not the kind of God who watches over
the world, hears prayers, and punishes sinners. It is in this sense that
Spinoza’s contemporaries called him an atheist: he made God
unrecognizable. He was also much bolder than other philosophers in
stating what many of them surely believed, that the Bible was a human
document that contained no privileged information about historical
events or the nature of divinity. It should therefore be read and
studied like any other book, with due attention to the motives of its
authors and the errors that had crept in throughout years of
transmission. This secular, rational approach to Scripture made Spinoza
arguably the father of Biblical criticism.
A
more unexpected corollary of Spinoza’s pantheism is that it eliminates
the possibility of free will, or of contingency of any kind. After all,
if everything is God, and God is absolute, then there is no way that
anything could happen differently from the way it does. If we knew
enough about how the world works, we “would find all things just as
necessary as are all those treated in mathematics.” Once again, at a
time when so much of human knowledge had been cast into doubt, the idea
of mathematical certainty was seductive. Spinoza longed for “the kind of
knowledge of God that we have of the triangle,” and he wrote his
“Ethics” in the form of a numbered list of axioms and deductions—a form
that he adopted from Euclid’s treatise on geometry. Spinoza’s definition
of “blessedness” was “the intellectual love of God,” in which the mind
sees the necessity of everything in the world as simply and indubitably
as Plato’s slave perceived the necessity of the Pythagorean theorem.
If
Spinoza seemed to take away humanity’s metaphysical freedom, however,
he gave it an unprecedented degree of political freedom in exchange. In
his “Theological-Political Treatise,” he praised the tolerant
multicultural society of Amsterdam and held it up as a model for the
world. But he wanted to go even further. Democracy, he argued, was “of
all forms of government the most natural, and the most consonant with
individual liberty.” He insisted on libertas philosophandi,
freedom of thought, and, while he granted that the state had the power
to establish the outward forms of religious worship, he adamantly
opposed any coercion of conscience. Each person had the right to decide
what God was and how best to serve him. Taken together, these beliefs
give Spinoza a claim to be considered the first great philosopher of
liberal democracy.
There is
something unearthly about Spinoza’s thought; similarly, there was
something unworldly about the man himself. Gottlieb writes that “his
kindness and nobility of character were legendary,” and he quotes
Bertrand Russell’s description of Spinoza as “the noblest and most
lovable of the great philosophers.” But this kind of irreproachability
can be hard to take, just as the intellectual love of God can seem
impossible to attain. (Isaac Bashevis Singer’s great story “The Spinoza
of Market Street” concerns a Warsaw intellectual who spends his life
trying to achieve that superhuman serenity, only to fall humiliatingly
in love with his nurse.)
In
“The Dream of Enlightenment,” Gottlieb writes with particular affection
about his fellow-Brits, the philosophers Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and
David Hume. Where Descartes and Spinoza tried to come to grips with
reality through purely deductive logic, the conventional story goes,
Locke and Hume valued the evidence of the senses. Their empiricism is
often taken to be a peculiarly British kind of virtue, defining a
difference between British and Continental philosophy that persists to
this day: on the one hand, skepticism of knowledge that has no basis in
experience and experiment; on the other, outlandish theories based on
unrestrained ratiocination.
Gottlieb
does not structure his book around this opposition, but he does show
that it has some basis in fact. Of all the philosophers he discusses,
his favorite seems to be Hume, who went furthest in rejecting the
deductive, geometrical ideal in philosophy. Spinoza wanted a knowledge
of the world that was as certain as the truths of mathematics, but Hume
pointed out that this was a category mistake. All our knowledge of the
world depends on experience, which means that it is contingent, not
absolute. We can, of course, trust that the sun will rise in the east
tomorrow, just as it did yesterday and every day before that. But we
can’t prove that it will rise in the same way we can prove that two plus
two is four. “ ’Tis not, therefore, reason, which is the guide of life,
but custom,” Hume concluded.
In
Hume’s view, Descartes’s program of demolishing the world through doubt
and then rebuilding it through logic is bound to fail. Instead, we have
to accept that our knowledge of the world is not absolute, as much as we
might like it to be. There is no surefire way to breach the gulf
between subjective and objective—what happens in my mind and what
happens out there in the world. This is equally true of the next world:
Hume was comfortably skeptical about religion’s promise of life after
death. Gottlieb tells the story of how James Boswell, the biographer of
Samuel Johnson, visited Hume on his deathbed, hoping to find that at the
last minute the philosopher would abjure his doubts and embrace
Christianity. But Boswell was disappointed to hear Hume affirm “that it
was a most unreasonable fancy that we should exist for ever.” Much of
the philosophy of the early modern period might now strike us as another
kind of unreasonable fancy. But we are still living with the problems
that these thinkers formulated and tried to solve. We are never quite as
modern as we think. ♦
No comments:
Post a Comment